No free lunch in search and optimization

No free lunch in search and optimization

This article is about mathematical analysis of computing.  For associated folklore, see No free lunch theorem.  

No free lunch in search and optimization_第1张图片

    The problem is to rapidly find a solution among candidates a, b, and c  that is as good as any other, where goodness is either 0 or 1. There are  eight instances ("lunch plates") fxyz of the problem, where x, y, and z  indicate the goodness of a, b, and c, respectively. Procedure  ("restaurant") A evaluates candidates in the order a, b, c, and B  evaluates candidates in reverse that order, but each "charges" 1  evaluation in 5 cases, 2 evaluations in 2 cases, and 3 evaluations in 1  case.

In computational complexity and optimization the no free lunch theorem  is a result that states that for certain types of mathematical  problems, the computational cost of finding a solution, averaged over  all problems in the class, is the same for any solution method. No  solution therefore offers a 'short cut'. In computing, there are  circumstances in which the outputs of all procedures solving a  particular type of problem are statistically identical. A colourful way  of describing such a circumstance, introduced by David Wolpert and William G. Macready in connection with the problems of search[1] and optimization,[2] is to say that there is no free lunch. Wolpert had previously derived no free lunch theorems for machine learning (statistical inference).[3]  Before Wolpert's article was published, Cullen Schaffer had summarized a  preprint version of this work of Wolpert's, but used different  terminology.[4]

In the "no free lunch" metaphor,  each "restaurant" (problem-solving procedure) has a "menu" associating  each "lunch plate" (problem) with a "price" (the performance of the  procedure in solving the problem). The menus of restaurants are  identical except in one regard – the prices are shuffled from one  restaurant to the next. For an omnivore  who is as likely to order each plate as any other, the average cost of  lunch does not depend on the choice of restaurant. But a vegan who goes to lunch regularly with a carnivore  who seeks economy might pay a high average cost for lunch. To  methodically reduce the average cost, one must use advance knowledge of  a) what one will order and b) what the order will cost at various  restaurants. That is, improvement of performance in problem-solving  hinges on using prior information to match procedures to problems.[2][4]

In formal terms, there is no free lunch when the probability distribution on problem instances is such that all problem solvers have identically distributed results. In the case of search, a problem instance is an objective function, and a result is a sequence of values obtained in evaluation of candidate solutions in the domain of the function. For typical interpretations of results, search is an optimization process. There is no free lunch in search if and only if the distribution on objective functions is invariant under permutation of the space of candidate solutions.[5][6][7] This condition does not hold precisely in practice,[6] but an "(almost) no free lunch" theorem suggests that it holds approximately.[8]

Contents

  • 1 Overview

  • 2 No free lunch (NFL)

    • 2.1 NFL and Kolmogorov randomness

  • 3 Formal synopsis of NFL

  • 4 Original NFL theorems

  • 5 Interpretations of NFL results

  • 6 Coevolutionary free lunches

  • 7 Notes

  • 8 See also

  • 9 External links

Overview

Some computational problems are solved by searching for good solutions in a space of candidate solutions. A description of how to repeatedly select candidate solutions for evaluation is called a search algorithm.  On a particular problem, different search algorithms may obtain  different results, but over all problems, they are indistinguishable. It  follows that if an algorithm achieves superior results on some  problems, it must pay with inferiority on other problems. In this sense  there is no free lunch in search.[1] Alternatively, following Schaffer,[4] search performance is conserved. Usually search is interpreted as optimization, and this leads to the observation that there is no free lunch in optimization.[2]

"The 'no free lunch' theorem of Wolpert and Macready," as stated in  plain language by Wolpert and Macready themselves, is that "any two  algorithms are equivalent when their performance is averaged across all  possible problems."[9]  The "no free lunch" results indicate that matching algorithms to  problems gives higher average performance than does applying a fixed  algorithm to all. Igel and Toussaint[6] and English[7]  have established a general condition under which there is no free  lunch. While it is physically possible, it does not hold precisely.[6]  Droste, Jansen, and Wegener have proved a theorem they interpret as  indicating that there is "(almost) no free lunch" in practice.[8]

To make matters more concrete, consider an optimization practitioner  confronted with a problem. Given some knowledge of how the problem  arose, the practitioner may be able to exploit the knowledge in  selection of an algorithm that will perform well in solving the problem.  If the practitioner does not understand how to exploit the knowledge,  or simply has no knowledge, then he or she faces the question of whether  some algorithm generally outperforms others on real-world problems. The  authors of the "(almost) no free lunch" theorem say that the answer is  essentially no, but admit some reservations as to whether the theorem  addresses practice.[8]

No free lunch (NFL)

A "problem" is, more formally, an objective function that associates candidate solutions with goodness values. A search algorithm takes an objective function as input and evaluates candidate solutions one-by-one. The output of the algorithm is the sequence of observed goodness values.[10][11]

Wolpert and Macready stipulate that an algorithm never reevaluates a  candidate solution, and that algorithm performance is measured on  outputs.[2]  For simplicity, we disallow randomness in algorithms. Under these  conditions, when a search algorithm is run on every possible input, it  generates each possible output exactly once.[7]  Because performance is measured on the outputs, the algorithms are  indistinguishable in how often they achieve particular levels of  performance.

Some measures of performance indicate how well search algorithms do at optimization  of the objective function. Indeed, there seems to be no interesting  application of search algorithms in the class under consideration but to  optimization problems. A common performance measure is the least index  of the least value in the output sequence. This is the number of  evaluations required to minimize the objective function. For some  algorithms, the time required to find the minimum is proportional to the  number of evaluations.[7]

The original no free lunch (NFL) theorems assume that all objective  functions are equally likely to be input to search algorithms.[2]  It has since been established that there is NFL if and only if, loosely  speaking, "shuffling" objective functions has no impact on their  probabilities.[6][7] Although this condition for NFL is physically possible, it has been argued that it certainly does not hold precisely.[6]

The obvious interpretation of "not NFL" is "free lunch," but this is  misleading. NFL is a matter of degree, not an all-or-nothing  proposition. If the condition for NFL holds approximately, then all  algorithms yield approximately the same results over all objective  functions.[7] Note also that "not NFL" implies only that algorithms are inequivalent overall by some measure of performance. For a performance measure of interest, algorithms may remain equivalent, or nearly so.[7]

NFL and Kolmogorov randomness

Almost all elements of the set of all possible functions (in the set-theoretic sense of "function") are Kolmogorov random,  and hence the NFL theorems apply to a set of functions almost all of  which cannot be expressed more compactly than as a lookup table that  contains a distinct (and random) entry for each point in the search  space. Functions that can be expressed more compactly (for example, by a  mathematical expression of reasonable size) are by definition not  Kolmogorov random.

Further, within the set of all possible objective functions, levels  of goodness are equally represented among candidate solutions, hence  good solutions are scattered throughout the space of candidates.  Accordingly, a search algorithm will rarely evaluate more than a small  fraction of the candidates before locating a very good solution.[11]

Almost all objective functions are of such high Kolmogorov complexity that they cannot arise.[5][7][11] There is more information in the typical objective function or algorithm than Seth Lloyd estimates the observable universe is capable of registering.[12]  For instance, if each candidate solution is encoded as a sequence of  300 0's and 1's, and the goodness values are 0 and 1, then most  objective functions have Kolmogorov complexity of at least 2300 bits,[13] and this is greater than Lloyd's bound of 1090 ≈ 2299  bits. It follows that not all of "no free lunch" theory applies to  physical reality. In a practical sense, algorithms "small enough" for  application in physical reality are superior in performance to those  that are not. It has also been shown that NFL results apply to  incomputable functions [14]

Formal synopsis of NFL

Y^X is the set of all objective functions f:XY, where X is a finite solution space and Y is a finite poset. The set of all permutations of X is J. A random variable F is distributed on Y^X. For all j in J, F o j is a random variable distributed on Y^X, with P(F o j = f) = P(F = f o j−1) for all f in Y^X.

Let a(f) denote the output of search algorithm a on input f. If a(F) and b(F) are identically distributed for all search algorithms a and b, then F has an NFL distribution. This condition holds if and only if F and F o j are identically distributed for all j in J.[6][7]  In other words, there is no free lunch for search algorithms if and  only if the distribution of objective functions is invariant under  permutation of the solution space.

The "only if" part was first published by C. Schumacher in his PhD  dissertation "Black Box Search – Framework and Methods" (The University  of Tennessee, Knoxville (2000)). Set-theoretic NFL theorems have  recently been generalized to arbitrary cardinality X and Y.[15]

Original NFL theorems

Wolpert and Macready give two principal NFL theorems, the first  regarding objective functions that do not change while search is in  progress, and the second regarding objective functions that may change.[2]

  • Theorem 1: For any pair of algorithms a1 and a2


    • \sum_f P(h_m^y | f, m, a_1) = \sum_f P(h_m^y | f, m, a_2).

In essence, this says that when all functions f are equally likely, the probability of observing an arbitrary sequence of m  values in the course of search does not depend upon the search  algorithm. Theorem 2 establishes a "more subtle" NFL result for  time-varying objective functions.

Interpretations of NFL results

A conventional, but not entirely accurate, interpretation of the NFL  results is that "a general-purpose universal optimization strategy is  theoretically impossible, and the only way one strategy can outperform  another is if it is specialized to the specific problem under  consideration".[16] Several comments are in order:

  • A general-purpose almost-universal optimizer exists theoretically. Each search algorithm performs well on almost all objective functions.[11]

  • An algorithm may outperform another on a problem when neither is specialized to the problem.  It may be that both algorithms are among the worst for the problem.  Wolpert and Macready have developed a measure of the degree of "match"  between an algorithm and a problem.[2] To say that one algorithm matches a problem better than another is not to say that either is specialized to the problem.

  • In practice, some algorithms reevaluate candidate solutions.  The superiority of an algorithm that never reevaluates candidates over  another that does on a particular problem may have nothing to do with  specialization to the problem.

  • For almost all objective functions, specialization is essentially accidental. Incompressible, or Kolmogorov random,  objective functions have no regularity for an algorithm to exploit.  Given an incompressible objective function, there is no basis for  choosing one algorithm over another. If a chosen algorithm performs  better than most, the result is happenstance.[11]  It should be noted that a Kolmogorov random function has no  representation smaller than a lookup table that contains a (random)  value corresponding to each point in the search space; any function that can be expressed more compactly is, by definition, not Kolmogorov random.

In practice, only highly compressible (far from random) objective  functions fit in the storage of computers, and it is not the case that  each algorithm performs well on almost all compressible functions. There  is generally a performance advantage in incorporating prior knowledge  of the problem into the algorithm. While the NFL results constitute, in a  strict sense, full employment theorems  for optimization professionals, it is important not to take the term  literally. For one thing, humans often have little prior knowledge to  work with. For another, incorporating prior knowledge does not give much  of a performance gain on some problems. Finally, human time is very  expensive relative to computer time. There are many cases in which a  company would choose to optimize a function slowly with an unmodified  computer program rather than rapidly with a human-modified program.

The NFL results do not indicate that it is futile to take "pot shots"  at problems with unspecialized algorithms. No one has determined the  fraction of practical problems for which an algorithm yields good  results rapidly. And there is a practical free lunch, not at all in  conflict with theory. Running an implementation of an algorithm on a  computer costs very little relative to the cost of human time and the  benefit of a good solution. If an algorithm succeeds in finding a  satisfactory solution in an acceptable amount of time, a small  investment has yielded a big payoff. If the algorithm fails, then little  is lost.

Coevolutionary free lunches

Wolpert and Macready have proved that there are free lunches in coevolutionary optimization.[9]  Their analysis "covers 'self-play' problems. In these problems, the set  of players work together to produce a champion, who then engages one or  more antagonists in a subsequent multiplayer game."[9]  That is, the objective is to obtain a good player, but without an  objective function. The goodness of each player (candidate solution) is  assessed by observing how well it plays against others. An algorithm  attempts to use players and their quality of play to obtain better  players. The player deemed best of all by the algorithm is the champion.  Wolpert and Macready have demonstrated that some coevolutionary  algorithms are generally superior to other algorithms in quality of  champions obtained. Generating a champion through self-play is of  interest in evolutionary computation and game theory. The results are inapplicable to coevolution of biological species, which does not yield champions.[9]

Notes

  1. Wolpert, D.H., Macready, W.G. (1995), No Free Lunch Theorems for Search, Technical Report SFI-TR-95-02-010 (Santa Fe Institute).

  2. Wolpert, D.H., Macready, W.G. (1997), "No Free Lunch Theorems for Optimization," IEEE Transactions on Evolutionary Computation 1, 67. http://ti.arc.nasa.gov/m/profile/dhw/papers/78.pdf

  3. Wolpert, David (1996), "“The Lack of A Priori Distinctions between Learning Algorithms," Neural Computation, pp. 1341–1390.

  4. Schaffer, Cullen (1994), "A conservation law for generalization performance," International Conference on Machine Learning, H. Willian and W. Cohen, Editors. San Francisco: Morgan Kaufmann, pp.259–265.

  5. Streeter, M. (2003) "Two Broad Classes of Functions for Which a No Free Lunch Result Does Not Hold," Genetic and Evolutionary Computation – GECCO 2003, pp. 1418–1430.

  6. Igel, C., and Toussaint, M. (2004) "A No-Free-Lunch Theorem for Non-Uniform Distributions of Target Functions," Journal of Mathematical Modelling and Algorithms 3, pp. 313–322.

  7. English, T. (2004) No More Lunch: Analysis of Sequential Search, Proceedings of the 2004 IEEE Congress on Evolutionary Computation, pp. 227–234. http://BoundedTheoretics.com/CEC04.pdf

  8. S. Droste, T.  Jansen, and I. Wegener. 2002. "Optimization with randomized search  heuristics: the (A)NFL theorem, realistic scenarios, and difficult  functions," Theoretical Computer Science, vol. 287, no. 1, pp. 131–144.

  9. Wolpert, D.H., and Macready, W.G. (2005) "Coevolutionary free lunches," IEEE Transactions on Evolutionary Computation, 9(6): 721–735

  10. A search algorithm also outputs the sequence of candidate solutions evaluated, but that output is unused in this article.

  11. English, T. M. 2000. "Optimization Is Easy and Learning Is Hard in the Typical Function," Proceedings of the 2000 Congress on Evolutionary Computation: CEC00, pp. 924–931. http://www.BoundedTheoretics.com/cec2000.pdf

  12. Lloyd, S. (2002) "Computational capacity of the universe," Physical Review Letters 88, pp. 237901–237904. http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0110141

  13. Li, M., and Vitányi, P. (1997) An Introduction to Kolmogorov Complexity and Its Applications (2nd ed.), New York: Springer.

  14. "Woodward, John R;  ",Computable and incomputable functions and search  algorithms,"Intelligent Computing and Intelligent Systems, 2009. ICIS  2009. IEEE International Conference on",1,,871-875,2009,IEEE

  15. Rowe, Vose, and Wright, "Reinterpreting No Free Lunch," Evolutionary Computation 17(1): 117–129

  16. Ho, Y.C., Pepyne, D.L. (2002), "Simple Explanation of the No-Free-Lunch Theorem and Its Implications," Journal of Optimization Theory and Applications 115, 549-570.

See also

  • Evolutionary informatics

  • Inductive bias

  • Occam's razor

  • Simplicity

  • Ugly duckling theorem

External links

  • http://www.no-free-lunch.org

  • Yin-Yang: No-Free-Lunch Theorems for Search

  • Radcliffe  and Surry, 1995, "Fundamental Limitations on Search Algorithms:  Evolutionary Computing in Perspective" (the first published paper on  NFL, available in various formats)

  • NFL publications by Thomas English

  • NFL publications by Christian Igel and Marc Toussaint

  • NFL and "free lunch" publications by Darrell Whitley

  • Publications by David Wolpert, William Macready, and Mario Koeppen on optimization and search

Categories:

  • Mathematical optimization

  • Theorems in computational complexity theory


你可能感兴趣的:(优化,搜索,search,free,Lunch,optimization,No,NFL,没有免费的我午餐)